The Anarchy of Thought

Charity begins at home. Perhaps. But then so does the long revolution against the Establishment.

Saturday, January 01, 2005

The Great Red Herring Posted by Hello
One dictionary defines the phrase 'red herring' as something that draws attention away from the central issue, and tells us that the origin of this expression is the practice of dragging a smoked herring along a track so as to throw off tracking dogs. The fear of the spread of 'Communism' acted as one such red herring during the McCarthy era in the US : instead of asking crucial questions such as what 'communism' was, and what its historical origins, socio-economic principles, and vision of human destiny were (which was the 'central issue'), the US administration tried to rouse the hysteria of the people against the Reds. It is arguable that in the late 1990s, the term Toleration has become the red herring for us with respect to various issues : rather than asking what these issues are really about, to what extent the claims associated with them are in/valid, how people whose lives are directly affected by them view them, and what inter-connected configurations of socio-economic-cultural questions these issues raise in their wake, we often behave as lazy school-children and try to wash our hands off such difficult home-work under the illusion that our laziness is justified by appealing to (an ill-defined) Tolerance.
Since, as an Old Master said, the beginning of wisdom lies in the definition of terms, I shall make one attempt towards 'wisdom' by first defining Toleration. I shall call a certain person to be tolerant of a belief or practice if she : (a) recognises that it is genuinely different from beliefs and practices located in her own world-view, (b) disagrees with the former, (c) and yet provides some space for the former to develop. Let us now apply this definition to two examples.
(1) To be 'tolerant' of Islam, it will not therefore do to go around entertaining vague notions of what Muslims believe and practice; nor can one say that the mere act of sharing a meal, watching a film, going to the same university, or playing a football match with a Muslim in itself amounts to 'toleration' (it goes without saying that the latter activities are most welcome, but they do not constitute toleration as I understand the term here). A person, David, can be said to be tolerant of a Muslim only when he first undertakes a careful study of the principles of Islam and develops some acquaintance with believers who practise these, and thereby comes to know what the precise differences are between his world-view and the life form called Islam. It may happen that in the process David realises that he and his Muslim acquaintance are living in two worlds separated by a wide chasm over several issues, and this will lead both of them to (re-)examine the validity of the claims that are raised in each other's world-views. In spite of these (possible) crucial differences, David must be willing to make some space, socially, culturally and legally, so as to ensure that the Muslim is able to live and flourish in the latter's religious world.
(2) To take an example from the other end of the spectrum, another person, Imran, can be said to be 'tolerant' of an atheist only when he is patient enough to know what the atheist really believes in (or disbelieves in), and how she lives in accordance with these dis/beliefs. To (apparently) live in harmony with an atheist, greeting her with a polite smile every morning, having coffee with her at the mid-day break, and going to the movies with her every weekend, while believing inwardly that she is morally corrupt or eternally damned, is not toleration but paternalism. To be truly tolerant of each other, both of them must engage themselves in a mutual process of (re-)examining the truth-claims that they respectively make within the horizons of their own worlds, and ask each other the hard, unsettling, and difficult questions that go with such (re-)examinations. To claim that they are 'tolerating' each other without having engaged in such investigations would be a parody of that term; this is but a thin and fragile 'tolerance' which can be used a mask for disguising the deep hatred and mutual distrust that may lie within. Finally, after such mutual inquiries, Imran must be willing to allow his atheist friend some conceptual and social space wherein she can develop her atheist convictions and live in accordance with them.
What have we observed in the above analysis? Firstly, the notion of tolerating someone must be carefully distinguished from the attitude that goes by the slogan : 'I do my thing, and you do your thing. Let us not disturb each other'. This slogan refers to a static state of affairs, a stalemate or a standoff between two parties, whereas toleration refers to an ongoing process, a never-ending dialogue between them. If I, who am religious, am to truly tolerate an atheist friend, it means that (a) I believe that she is mistaken in holding some of her beliefs, (b) wish, nevertheless, to engage her in a continuous dialogue over these beliefs, (c) and yet am willing to allow her space to develop her views. Toleration, as I understand the term, is therefore not a passive state but an active response, a desire to learn more about the other, and this is the reason why (b) is important. I am said to truly tolerate members of communities to which I do not belong only when I simultaneouly affirm (a), (b), and (c). To accept (b) and (c) without (a) would mean that I am shying away from the hard home-work of analysing truth-claims, to accept (a) and (c) without (b) would mean that I am hiding my lack of desire to know the other under the cloak of 'toleration', and finally to accept (a) and (b) without (c) would mean that I view the others as a constant threat at my horizons and cannot coexist with their otherness.
In short, I understand 'toleration' and 'dia-logue' as co-terminous, which is to say that I truly tolerate only those people with whom I am engaged in a constant dialogue. For example, I cannot be said, strictly speaking, to tolerate Tibetan Buddhists, anti-abortionists, Japanese Shintoists, or Chinese communists. The reason for this is not because I wish to exterminate them or cast them into cold dungeons (I do not) but because I do not know anyone belonging to any of the above communities, and, therefore, cannot obviously enter into a living dia-logue with them. I can, of course, still say that I tolerate Tibetan Buddhists but this 'toleration' would only be in a trivial and formally empty sense. On the other hand, I can say that I tolerate Anglican Christians, Marxists, Buddhists, agnostics, and atheists because not only do I know some Anglican, Marxist, Buddhists, agnostic, and atheist friends but also because I am engaged, every now and then, in a mutual process of discussing their views with mine.
Indeed, the slogan, 'I do my own thing, you do yours', far from being a manifestation of 'tolerance' can be used to mask pernicious forms of seething underlying hatred. In saying this, I do not imply that we must jump to the other extreme slogan which goes as, 'I know it better than you do', and which tries to legitimise all sorts of 'interventionist' activity. All of this brings out the dire need of (c); we must be willing, in spite of our mutual differences, some of which can be radical, to engage ourselves in the never-ending process of (re-)negotiating and (re-)establishing the social and cultural boundaries which mark off certain zones as belonging to 'us' and 'them'. This process can be given the shorthand term 'toleration'.

Friday, December 31, 2004

Now is the Time Posted by Hello




Sometimes your ability to clearly express your thoughts is limited by the vocabulary of the linguistic world that you inhabit. In English, for example, this is especially the case when it comes to temporal expressions since we have to make do with only one word 'time'. Greek, for example, on the other hand, has two words chronos and kairos. Chronos corresponds quite closely to our day to day notion of time, that is, of time as sequential, numerical, and chronological. It is this time that we measure with a clock (or a 'chronometer'), and is orderly and predictable. Therefore, according to this understanding of time, today's date is January 1.
Kairos, on the other hand, cannot quite be translated into English with a single word, but refers to a period of time when something special or unique happens : it is the right moment, the critical stage, or the opportune time. Kairos time is that which marks out a period of disruption in the normal flow of events, a time when the ground is shifting, and the old habits and beliefs are undergoing a change. In this sense, we think of January 1 (otherwise just a point or a dot on the calendar) as a 'new way', or a 'new opening'.

Is it 'intolerant' to 'convert' other people? Posted by Hello



In our bygone days of youth, we used to have magnificent dreams, dreams that we would soon dispel the darkness from the farthest reaches of the planet, and make the world a happy place for everyone to live in. Today, in our senescence, we instead find ourselves sitting by the fire nodding our heads as we sigh over our heroic but failed attempts. We have been overtaken by fresh blood which lampoons our efforts alleging that we were simply trying to mask our sinister intentions behind grandiloquent slogans. Some of them continue to live uneasily among the broken-down relics of our massive structures, some pick-and-mix fragments from these relics in order to build their own imposing monuments and often deliberately hide their indebtness to us, and some lament that all building activity must now be given up as pointless. Meanwhile, the writing on the wall (that is, whatever is left of the Wall, in Berlin or elsewhere) is clear : All conversion activity is a form of intolerance. Thank you very much, we don't need any more missionaries after the mess that you have made of this lovely, green world of ours. Just leave us alone, will you?

'We' therefore stand accused at the altar of the Goddess (or, God?) called Tolerance. As counsel for the defence in this post, I plead guilty to the crime of often having used dishonest, disreputable, atrocious and violent means in our desire to convert. I willingly and sincerely accept the corrective punishment in some 'penitentiary centre' of having to rethink over what went wrong that led us to resort to violent means in our desire to reach out to the others. However, I also state in the same breath that we must most carefully and resolutely separate (a) the desire to convert others from (b) the tools or methods that are used to express this desire. Indeed, I shall argue more than this : it is possible that even our accusers who now sit smugly on the benches out there, smiling cynically at us, have not completely given up (a), they have only changed the nature of (b) that they use.

The desire to bring others around to our point of view is a very common human desire, though there are significant differences among human beings as to the extent to which they may have this desire. I shall refer to people who have this desire, to a greater or lesser extent, as Evangelists. More specifically, I shall define an Evangelist as a person who (E1) believes that she has a certain message to offer to the world which she thinks is currently engaging in behaviour that is terribly dangerous, or holding beliefs which are highly misguided, and (E2) hopes that the world will come around from its current state of affairs by accepting her message and undergoing a process of reformation. Different Evangelists will, however, express (E1) and (E2) in divergent ways : for some, all human beings must hear this message, for others, it is sufficient that only a few come to hear/accept it; again, for some, it is most urgent that this message is heard by everyone immediately, for others, it may be reasonable to expect that it will take a few generations before it becomes widely-known; for some, it is necessary that the others, after hearing the message, actually undergo a metanoia and cross, once and for all, the threshold that clearly separates the old life from the new, for others, it may be enough to have sown some seeds of doubt in the minds and hearts of the hearers.

Let me explain these differences by contrasting a woman's (possible) relationship to feminist theory with my personal liking for Beethoven's symphony No 9. A feminist is, roughly speaking, a woman who believes that all women who inhabit religious world-views have their lives greviously damaged since such englobing perspectives are rooted in patriarchal assumptions. As for my like of that symphony of Beethoven, I believe that listening to it would be a good experience for other people, if they had the means and the time to do so. Therefore, both a feminist and I are Evangelists, but now note the differences between us. Firstly, the feminist would like to ensure that everyone (that is, every man and every woman) in this world comes to hear about her analysis of the patriarchal foundations of human society; as for myself, I would admit only too readily that for a beggar it is infinitely more important to save money to buy a loaf of bread than to listen to that symphony. That is, the feminist's Evangelism is universal in a sense that mine is not. Secondly, for the feminist it is extremely important that every human being comes to know about her analyses as soon as possible (and, even better, accepts them too), whereas I really couldn't care how many more years it takes before everyone on this planet listens to that Beethoven symphony.

Indeed, it is may be the case that there is something of an Evangelist slumbering deep even within those of us who may otherwise claim not to have any such evangelical intentions. To be sure, we may not quite have the sense of urgency that (many) feminists do, but in our daily interactions with our friends and relatives, and in the processes of telling them what is right and what is not, what we like and what we do not, what we would want them to like and what we would not, we may be living, unbeknownst to ourselves, very much as Evangelists. On the basis of this discussion, then, let us ask : is every attempt at conversion, or, to use my terms, at Evangelism (in the sense (a) above) necessarily ruled out by a vague appeal to the divinity of Tolerance? If we reply in the affirmative, it would imply that we must ban all feminist literature, as well prohibit the (the thousands of) subtle and express attempts at Evangelism that we make on a daily basis with those who live with and around us. Hold on tight, for here is more trouble to come.

(1) There are anti-smoking Evangelists all over the United Kingdom who wish to have smoking banned in public places. That is, they believe that something is terribly wrong with a world where smoking is allowed in public spaces (E1), and they campaign for a different world where people will come to see the terrible mess that they have made by allowing such smoking, and will repent and change their laws (E2).

(2) Marxist theorists have regularly pointed out how religious systems are embedded within inegalitarian structures, and how the latter have entrenched themselves even more firmly by making use of legitimising doctrines provided to them by the former. They believe that currently a large proportion of human beings lives within oppressive systems (E1), and would wish to bring it about that these latter are dismantled and more 'transparent' ones are established in their place (E2).

(3) Parents are Evangelists too, and if Evangelism is to be forbidden, so too must parenthood for parents wish to bring up their children according to a specific set of norms and values. For example, if you are born into an orthodox Jewish family, you shall be brought up as a Jew (and be taught that 'being Jewish' is a live option for you in a sense that 'being Marxist' is not); and exactly a similar pattern of argument applies irrespective of whether the family you are born into is Muslim, Hindu, Christian, Taoist, Sikh, Confucian, neo-Pagan, Shinto, Theosophist, Anthroposophist, Buddhist, Jaina and so on. An atheist couple may like to self-congratulate themselves with the belief that they have escaped the conceptual net of this argument; as a matter of fact, however, they have not. It is very likely that an atheist couple will bring up their children to be atheists, and would be, I strongly suspect, mortally grieved to learn that one of their children has become, say, a Muslim. Whether explicitly or implicitly, parents believe that there are certain aspects of the world 'out there' that are nasty, bad, brutish, and dangerous (E1), and they either wish to (actively) change those aspects so that the world becomes a 'better place' for their children to live in, or, at least, (passively) to keep their children away from them (E2). It is impossible to avoid the conclusion that every type of education (whether it is religious, secular, liberal, post-liberal, feminist, post-feminist, atheistic, agnostic, Marxist, critical Marxist, and so on) is, at some level or the other, a form of Evangelism, whether this is kept disguised or made explicit. Therefore, to rule that (a), the desire to convert others, must be declared illegal is tantamount to saying that all schools and universities must be razed to the ground.
(4) There are some thinkers in the 'Western' world, usually (though not necessarily) from an atheist background, who claim that in discussing crucial ('public'/'scientific') issues such as abortion, euthanasia, capital punishment, and stem-cell research, people should not make appeals to ('private'/'traditional') religious sources. Therefore, such thinkers believe that there is something very wrong with a world where such appeals are made (E1), and claim that we should strive to establish a new world where these appeals are declared to be illegal (E2). Consequently, such atheism too is a form of Evangelism, this time an Evangelism which believes that things would work out better for everyone if it were possible to remove voices stemming from a religious context from the 'naked public square'.
(5) The contemporary nation-state itself engages in an active 'mission' of Evangelisation in order to spread its secular nationalism through a process in which older religious-sounding terms are 'translated', wherever possible, into their secularised versions. For example, martyrdom is redefined as death in a war waged by the nation-state, blasphemy is now rather to be understood as treason against it, and the notion of worship is reconceptualised as the ultimate loyalty to it, a loyalty that is to be expressed through national anthems, commemoration ceremonies, and the retelling of the lives of its historical founders.

In short, if we say that (a), namely, the desire to convert others, must be rooted out and branded a form of intolerance, all feminist literature must at once be consigned to the flames, all anti-smoking Evangelists imprisoned, Marxist theorists driven underground, parenthood abolished, the views of (militant) atheists proscribed, and the very existence of the nation-state declared illegitimate. Would that not simply become yet another example of how some of the greatest types of intolerance in human history have been sanctioned in the 'name of Tolerance'?
Let us now take up what I shall call the 'litmus-test' of anti-Evangelism : Is postmodernism, and particularly the version of it that (apparently) sets its face against all activities of conversion as being 'imperialistic', 'paternalistic' and 'totalitarian', itself a kind of Evangelism? To be such a postmodernist you must (a) believe that there is something grievously wrong with the world 'out there' where believers in some meta-narrative or the other such as Muslims, Christians, Buddhists, Marxists, atheists, 'scientists' and so on are trying their best to convert one another, and (b) either have a mild occasional wish that the world was not such, or have a stronger desire to somehow (though you-know-not-how) bring it about that such conversion activity came to an immediate halt. Now in terms of my definition above, (a) here corresponds to E1, and (b) to E2, which is to say that this version of postmodernism too is a form of Evangelism. In fact, the only absolutely consistent non-Evangelical postmodernist would be a person who withdraws to the silence-wrapped heights of the Himalayas straight-away and never utters, ever again, a single word for the remainder of her life. Anything that she might say thereafter (either as an affirmation or as a denial; or as a denial of either of these alternatives; or as a denial of a denial of .....) will be taken as evidence, against her alleged non-Evangelism, in a court of law.
Why is it the case, then, that some world-views seem to be more Evangelical than others? For example, it is more common to come across a Christian, a secular nationalist, or a Marxist Evangelist than, say a Hindu or a Jaina one (or, at least, this was the case until very recently). The reason for this is that Evangelism belongs to the 'intrinsic core' of beliefs of certain world-views, while in others it may be an optional extra that lies at the periphery. For example, if you believe that human beings have only one life-time in which to undergo a decisive change from the present empirical conditions of finitude to an infinitely better state to be established in the future, you are more likely to exhibit greater Evangelical zeal than someone who believes that this perfection can be attained over several life-times. Therefore, as a Marxist it might be imperative for you to go out into the world straight-away and try to make Marxists out of everyone; as a Hindu, on the other hand, you could sit at home and actively hope that those who are, say, Jews and atheists in this birth will, during and over a period of future world-orders, come to be born into a Hindu family, and thereby proceed towards final liberation. This, incidentally, is not to claim that Hinduism is more 'tolerant' than Marxism, for the basic issue in this context is the validity of the truth-claims that are being raised within the Marxist and the Hindu horizons respectively. If a Marxist can provide sufficient reason why a Hindu should not have epistemic confidence in the doctrine of karma and reincarnation, this Evangelical act on the part of the Marxist should rather be viewed as being truly 'tolerant', for this is the act of bringing the Hindu out of her former ignorance to the truth of the matter concerning this doctrine.
In a similar fashion, a Buddhist who believes that the route to liberation from this world of suffering is through the four Noble Truths, which apply to all sentient beings, is likely to display greater Evangelical fervour than someone who thinks that there is, in fact, no such route, or someone who believes, for whatever reasons, that this liberation is possible through alcoholism, or someone who claims that even if one knows about such a route, one should not reveal it to one's neighbours. Again, an atheist who believes that she has a 'duty towards humankind' to expose the illusions that religious believers suffer from will tend to have more Evangelical zest than an atheist who believes that religious folk are in any case incorrigible and should be left to their own devices.
In short, different Evangelists display varying levels of Evangelical enthusiasm, and this is partly related to the differences among the world-views that they inhabit. Let us now move on to (b), that is, the question of the variety of tools that people use (and have used) to express their desire to convert others to their view-point, and it is actually here that most of the trouble starts brewing.
Historically speaking, it is true that Evangelists of a religious persuasion have often used force and compulsion to bring people over to their world-views. Muslims and Christians, in particular, have received quite a bad press in this matter and it is this historical record that rouses the strong passions of many people whenever they come across the phrase 'religious conversion' (which is a more specific case of what I have termed Evangelism and which includes 'conversion to atheism' too). However, in order that we do not commit the fallacy of mistaking what is contingent for what is necessary, we must be patient and willing to (a) find out if there really is a logically necessary connection between the desire for conversion and the use of disreputable and violent tools in that specific religion, and (b) to read what inhabitants of that religion have themselves said about those specific historical instances where violent tools may have been used. To take the case of Christianity, for example, a careful study of its doctrinal history will reveal, firstly, that there is no such connection, and secondly, that many Christians themselves have come to recognise that certain activities that earlier went under the label of 'conversion' were, in fact, betrayals of the Gospel. There is, in other words, no reason to believe that all religious conversion necessarily goes with violent means; much of conversion activity is carried out today through the means of persuasion, discussion, presentation of one's views, and dialogue with others. Indeed, if anything, it is the opposite impression that may be need to corrected in some contexts; that is, we may need to be re-assured that in spite of all the Hitlers and the Stalins of the world, the desire to convert other people to (some kind of) an atheist world-view need not necessarily be expressed through deceitful and violent tools.
Let us take one specific example from the Indian context. The question is sometimes raised, especially in political and legal circles, as to whether or not (Indian) Muslims and Christians should be given the right to convert non-Muslims and non-Christians (and this question acts as a sure red flag to the bulls of historical research who routinely point out instances of Muslim/Christian 'intolerance'). To rephrase the question in my terms, should Indian Muslims and Indian Christians be given the right to Evangelise?, and in order to show why they should be given this right, I shall point out some of the implications of declaring Evangelisation to be illegal.
(1) Let us say that a certain group declares that such Evangelisation is illegal. This group would then have to make at least one claim, X such that X : Muslims and Christians should not be allowed to Evangelise. Now X can be further 'broken down' into X1 : There is something very wrong about living in a world where Muslims and Christians have this right (which corresponds to E1), and X2 : We must do something to bring it about that they do not enjoy this right in the future (and this corresponds to E2). Therefore, those who put forward X are themselves, according to my terms, Evangelists, and having put forward this claim X, members of this group would themselves have to first Evangelise others over to their view, X. That is, if I happen to be neither Muslim nor Christian and yet refuse to accept X (for example, I could be a militant atheist in Bangalore or a Marxist in Kolkata who is aware that my right to Evangelise others to my atheism or my Marxism may be taken away, by subsequent extension of X), this group will first have to Evangelise me, either through persuasion or physical threats , so that I come to accept X. Therefore, the very act of declaring Evangelisation to be illegal presupposes that Evangelisation is not, in fact, illegal! One way out of this tangle is, of course, to make a difference between 'two types of Evangelisation' by putting forward the claim Y, such that Y : Only non-Muslims and non-Christians should be allowed to Evangelise one another. Even in this case, however, one would still need to Evangelise, only that this time it will be the Muslims and the Christians who would not readily accept Y and who will, therefore, have to be evangelised! Once again, then, the proclaimed illegality of Evangelism at one (lower?) level would be presupposed by its assumed legality at another (higher?) level.
(2) It is possible that the group that makes the claim X is from some kind of a 'Hindu' background (though the question of how justified the group would be in identifying itself as 'Hindu' is a different matter). Suppose, however, that there is another group, members of which call themselves Indian 'secularists' and who make the same claim X : a similar argument to the one above could then be made against this latter group too. It can be argued that these people too have their own brand of Evangelism, an Evangelism to spread 'secularism' (ES) throughout the length and the breadth of the country. Therefore, if Muslims and Christians are not be allowed their own Evangelisms (EM, EC) it must first be pointed out precisely what it is about these latter Evangelisms that cannot be accomodated within the broader framework of a 'secular' state. It may be replied that EM and EC make 'absolute truth-claims', and such claims cannot be permissible since they threaten to tear apart its secular fabric. Possibly so, but we must also keep in mind that ES itself goes with an absolute truth-claim A, such that A : It is an absolute truth that given the socio-cultural context of India, only that secularism that 'respects all religions' and makes no discrimination among citizens on the basis of their religious background can be accepted. I do not deny, of course, that there are people who would reject A, but it is a fact that most people who do accept A accept it as an 'absolute' non-negotiable claim. If that be so, one would need to show specifically what it is about the 'absolute' claims of Islam and Christianity that immediately disqualifies them from being raised within the horizons of the 'secular' nation. Moreover, Marxist and feminist theory can be easily 'translated', though, of course, in very different ways, into sets of absolute truth-claims too; therefore, unless Indian Marxists and Indian feminists qua Marxists and feminists are to be banned from 'public life', there is not much plausibility for prohibiting EM and EC on the mere grounds that these latter come packaged with 'absolute' claims.
(3) One aspect of Indian secularism is that the nation-state shall 'respect' all religions, and it can be argued that in order to respect a certain world-view the very least that one must do is not to actually hinder those who inhabit it from carrying out certain practices that directly follow from its 'innermost core' of beliefs. To take the case of Christianity, one belief that belongs to this core is that God's love for humanity has been revealed through the Crucifixion-and-Resurrection of Jesus Christ, and that those who have accepted, in faith, this Good News should spread it to their friends and neighbours. Therefore, a Christian could argue that she wishes to deliver this News to those around her, and claim that she would not be able to identify herself as Christian in a nation-state where she is forbidden to do so. That is, Indian secularism can be said to 'respect' Christianity only when it allows EC, for EC is not an 'optional extra' but belongs to the very heart of the Christian scheme of things (and similar arguments apply for EM, and, as I have pointed out above, for (Indian) Marxism and feminism too).
(4) Let us say that someone wishes to remain within the context of Indian secularism (as defined above) and yet denies (the validity of) EC and EM. This could be for various reasons : it may be so that the person has a vague sense of uneasiness with any world-view that makes 'absolute' claims, or may be she objects to certain beliefs and practices within the Christian or Muslim world-views, or perhaps she believes that all religious belief is a pernicious error, and so on. This is a very different type of argument as compared to the ones that we have examined in (1) - (3). The issues that we were discussing earlier were centred around the question of whether any Evangelisation is to be allowed within the socio-political contours of the Indian nation-state, and we came to the conclusion that the declaration that all Evangelisation is, in principle, illegal would subvert itself (for this declaration itself would then be a masked form of Evangelisation). This time, however, we come to the more exciting, and also infinitely more difficult, question of which type of Evangelisation is the correct one : is it the Evangelisation activities carried out by the (Indian) Marxists, the secularists, the Christians, the Muslims, the (militant) atheists, the feminists, the Hindus, or the Buddhists? Here we must be careful not to confuse two logically very different forms of parity : legal parity and epistemic parity. By the former, I mean that all the above-mentioned world-views, and consequently the forms of Evangelisations associated with them, enjoy equal legal sanction from the nation-state. However, it is not for the nation-state to declare that inhabitants of one specific world-view should also regard all other world-views as being on epistemic par with one another. For example, an Indian Muslim may come to the conclusion, (possibly) through a study of Islam and discussions with, say, Hindus, Marxists, and Christians, that Islam is for her a doxastic practice that places within a comprehensive conceptual structure every facet of her existence in a manner that Hinduism, Marxism and Christianity are incapable of doing. And, of course, the (Indian) Hindu, the Marxist, and the Christian can all come to their own respective conclusions about why their specific world-view, and the consequent Evangelisation, is such a 'comprehensive conceptual structure' for them. It is crucial to note here that there is nothing intrinsic to the notion of 'Indian secularism' that can make such declarations invalid. That is, though (Indian) Hindus, Muslims, Christians, and Marxists are all given equal legal sanction to practise their Evangelisations, people belonging to any one of these forms of life cannot be compelled to declare that their own and those of others around them enjoy epistemic parity as well. An Indian Marxist can continue to make --- at the epistemic level --- the 'absolute' claim that all religious belief is a dangerous illusion, while allowing --- at the legal level --- others around her to practise their own Evangelisations, whether or not these latter are religious, atheist, or agnostic. There is nothing 'intolerant' about this; ironically, it is the refusal to patiently listen to the Marxist and to take her truth-claim seriously by making invocations to the elusive authority of Tolerance that should be regarded as a form of intolerance.
(5) Finally, a tricky case from the long and turbulent history of the Christian Evangelical enterprise in India : Christian Evangelists are often accused of making 'converts' out of Hindus and Muslims by promising them financial incentives. Let us examine the issue from four different stand-points :
(a) One Christian Evangelist could put forward the following argument : "If I were to see a hungry man on the street and I had some money in my pocket, I could not care less what religion he puts down as his own on the census form. I shall immediately see in him 'Christ, hungry and naked', and I shall try to help him. This help can be of two types. One is, of course, the immediate one of giving him some food to eat. The other is the more enduring one of trying to find some job that he can take up, and thereby earn some money for his needs. Now it may so happen that after some time, this man on the street becomes curious to know what exactly it is about my set of beliefs that led me to help him on that day; and then I shall introduce him to the Good News of Christianity. To carry on, he may actually accept, in faith, this News and be baptised into the community, or he may not. If, however, he does receive baptism, he has done this out of his own free choice; there is not the slightest element of compulsion involved in the process. What you might now argue is that when I helped that man on the street that day I did this with the hope that he would finally become a Christian someday. I do not, in fact, deny that this is the case, but I ask you to tell me what precisely is wrong with having such a hope. Unless you can give me reasons to believe that the following truth-claim X is invalid, where X : Christ, our Lord, died for us, and He wishes us to turn to Him, I do not see why I should abandon the hope that others around me will, in fact, go to Him when I tell them about Him."
(b) Another Christian Evangelist, possibly a variety that goes under the label 'Franciscan', could pick up the argument from there and chirp in : "You are probably making a distinction between, roughly speaking, 'spirituality' and 'economics' which leads you to believe that the latter has nothing to do with the former. As a matter of fact, however, the way in which I understand my Christianity asks me to believe that no such separation is possible, so that when I feed and clothe a hungry beggar on the street this act is very much a part of my 'spirituality'. Therefore, when you (implicitly) demand that I talk about God only within the churches and not help those on the streets, you are effectively demanding that I stop being Christian. This demand, however, would go against the very foundations of your 'Indian secularism'."
(c) A third Christian Evangelist now comes in : "You are possibly arguing that any act of helping the beggar must be prohibited if this act can be shown to flow from certain (background) motives. In my case, the 'motive' is that I wish to obey the commandment to help the beggar, a commandment which was (derivatively) given to me by my Lord, Jesus Christ, when he (ultimately) ordered us to love our neighbours. In that case, however, neither would a Hindu, a Buddhist, a Muslim, an atheist, or a Marxist, be allowed to help a beggar since in each of these cases the act would flow from some motive or the other. Even if an Indian claims to have no 'world-view' whatsoever and yet helps the beggar, she would still be acting out of a certain 'motive' which in her case would be : I am motivated to help this beggar by my belief that it is a good thing to do so. Therefore, if you want to claim that the mere existence of a motive is sufficient reason to forbid the act of helping a beggar, you shall have to be more specific and now say that no such act is to be allowed only if this follows from a specifically Christian motive. This move, however, cannot be made unless you can show what is so disreputable about this motive that it must be declared to be illegitimate within the horizons of 'Indian secularism'."
(d) A fourth Christian Evangelist may wish to conclude this discussion with these remarks : "A lot depends on how that term 'incentive' is understood. Some of us in the past may have put forward financial gains to Hindus and Muslims with the hope that this promise will necessarily activate faith in the Gospel in them. They were certainly wrong in this matter of using deceitful means for a living faith in the reality of God can only come as a divine gift; it cannot be earned or bought through any human tools. However, some of us have often invited Hindus and Muslims to be a part of our community and share in our liturgical practices of worshipping God whose love for us was revealed through the Son, Jesus Christ. They have become our truly intimate neighbours, and we are commanded by our Lord to love them, and surely, one aspect of loving them involves helping them with their financial needs. Unless you wish to claim that it is wrong to offer financial help to your own close friends, you cannot demand that we stop doing the same and not help these new friends of ours if they may have such needs. This is not to say, as you falsely believe or wrongly suspect, that we give them money in order that they may become our friends; rather, it is because they have (already) been made our friends-in-Christ, and not solely by us but ultimately by Christ Himself, that we wish to give them monetary help (and, for that matter, any other help that we are capable of). By misjudging the nature of cause-and-effect involved in this process, you wrongly think that the alleged 'incentive' comes before a person becomes a member of our community, whereas, in truth, it comes after."
Let me summarise : (1) The prosecution has not made its case that the desire to convert must be made illegal, not least because the people who argue for this move are themselves trying to convert others (either through 'rational persuasion' or by 'legal force') to their view! (2) The (legitimate) demand that violent methods be given up in converting others must not be confused with the claim that the desire to convert others is itself illegitimate. (3) Nor must it be thought that Evangelism is always connected with the propagation of 'religious belief'; not to mention the (non-religious) feminist and the militant atheist, almost every kind of a (possibly non-religious) postmodernist is also an Evangelist. Therefore, if we still wish to hold on to the notion that Evangelism (or 'conversion') is a form of intolerance, we must be willing to accept that this intolerance applies to militant atheism and (almost every version of) postmodernism too. (4) To claim that members of certain traditions such as Islam (or, for that matter, Marxism) have used, in the past, violent means to propagate their views may be very good history. However, to jump (or, even more strongly, to argue that this jump is logically necessitated) from this sound historical observation to the unwarranted conclusion that all the truth-claims made within Islam (or Marxism) are thereby falsified at one stroke is but a manifestation of slipshod thinking. Just as Newton's 'law of universal gravitation' is not falsified by the mere fact that a tyrant of a school teacher beats his students for forgetting it, so too the question of the validity of the claims made within a world-view and the historical record of how these claims were propagated are two issues that are, and must be kept, conceptually distinct.

Thursday, December 30, 2004

The Forgotten Darkness Posted by Hello




Now that the long winter nights become brighter than ever with halogen lights, here are eighteen of my songs for the Forgotten Darkness :

(1)

What does one beggar do
when another beggar comes to him
asking for money?
perhaps this is a meaningless question
or perhaps such things happen only in the movies
but as for my beggar
well, he can't do nothing at all
but stare into the eyes of his friend
while above both of them
the despicable winter sun
gently sinks into their tired eyes.

(2)

At the water's edge the beggar
sings the same song a million times
sometimes it is good
to hear your own voice
every noon the kite flies
round and round and round
screaming out her heart
for a fragile peace
that was never hers.

(3)

In this world
there are but three sorrows
one that is real
one that is unreal
and one that lies sleeping
in the abyss of your dark eyes
unknown even to you.

(4)

New year's Eve
the old beggar makes a fire
out of old lottery tickets
and on New year's Day
she changes the old water
in the vase with plastic flowers.

(5)

Christmas evening
The young man gives the beggar
His empty unused wallet.

(6)

Handing him a ten pound note
The girl asks the beggar
To give nine pounds back to her.

(7)

The old dog looks into the beggar’s bowl
And wonders which
Of the ten coins are for him.

(8)

The beggar has fifteen coins
He needs just one more
To teach his dog
How to play Chinese checkers.

(9)

Winter morning
At the temple
A long row of devotees
The beggar too takes out his three coins
And places them in a long row.

(10)

Busy market-square
The beggar and his violin
He is not very good at Mozart
But in this world
At least his dog has ears.

(11)

They say that the old temple
has now run out of priests
and I used to think
that there will be priests
as long as there are beggars.

(12)

Sunday afternoon
The beggar and his dog go fishing
The beggar prays to God
That he might catch some fish
The dog prays to the fish
That they might get caught.

(13)

December night
Taking a match stick from the beggar
She tries to light her cigarette.

(14)

Girl walks along the gaily-lit shops
And her perfume reminds the beggar
Of some of his own forgotten dreams.

(15)

The brown beggar comes to her door
and she screams : 'Do not disturb me now,
can you not see that I am praying?'
so he goes away wondering
to whom he should pray.

(16)

Even the bitterness of Spring
is a part of her beauty
in the city angry cars have become
rats that have forgotten their holes
only the sky now remembers
the cold weight of the black hunger.

(17)

When the horses come riding
riding through the December fog
dust and mist shall become one
and you shall then see
on her emaciated face
layer after layer
of terrified sunset.

(18)

Black train goes
rushing over the blacker rails
steel on steel
bone with bone
fire from fire
madness in madness
and after the train is gone
the rail tracks remain
as lonely
as speechless
as ever.



Living Along Fault-lines Posted by Hello





My personal interest in that overburdened phrase ‘Islam and the West’ lies in the question of the relation between the two concepts of ‘religion’ and ‘culture’. Indeed, I believe that the ‘clash’ between Islam and the West ultimately revolves around different understandings of this relation. One way of investigation this relation is to start off by trying to define ‘religion’ and ‘culture’. However, as is well known to students of sociology and anthropology, this attempt can easily get bogged down in endless debate and controversy over what these concepts refer to. Therefore, I shall follow an alternative method : instead of trying to define these concepts, I shall outline the different ways in which people have, historically speaking, understood their mutual relation (or non-relation/anti-relation). Sometimes even when we cannot precisely define two terms A and B, an understanding of the relation between A and B can throw some light on what A and B themselves are.

A survey of the religious history of humanity reveals that there are four major ways in which the relation between ‘religion’ and ‘culture’ has been understood and put into socio-religious practice.

(A)

Religion Against Culture

This type emphasises the opposition between religion and culture. Whatever be the customs of the society in which the religious person lives, whatever be the human achievements that it conserves, religion is seen as being opposed to all of them. There is therefore a strict either-or between religion and culture. To be religious means that one must set his/her face completely against society.

Here are two examples :


(a) In the Graeco-Roman world, Christianity was totally opposed to what it perceived to be the idolatry of pagan culture. One of the popular Roman complaints against Christianity was that it was drawing young men and women from society and setting them against the ancient heritage of Greek civilisation. This was also true in the Mediaeval Ages when Christian monks and nuns rejected the world of culture as inherently corrupt and implicated in a sinister deal with devilish forces.

(b) Buddhism rejected the Brahmanic system of organisation of individual and social existence. With this rejection of casteism, went a whole-sale opposition to Brahmanic culture and everything that it entailed. The reason why Buddhism ultimately became a heterodox form of Hinduism was not because of its denial of the existence of 'God' (there were, and still are, Hindus who do not believe in 'God') but because of its opposition to contemporary culture. In other words, Buddhism was opposed not just to the Upanisadic-theological dimension of Hinduism but also to the cultural values it propagated.


(B)

Religion Of Culture

This type emphasises the fundamental agreement between religion and culture. A religious founder is regarded as the great hero of human culture and history and his (or her, in some rare cases) life and teachings are regarded as the greatest human achievement. It is believed that he brings to fulfilment the cultural aspirations of humankind. He confirms and supports whatever is best in culture and guides civilisation to its correct goal. Religion therefore is a part of culture in the sense that it includes the social heritage that must be transmitted and conserved.

Here are two examples :

(a) In the Mediaeval ages in Europe, the Catholic Church presented itself as fulfilling the best and the noblest elements in pagan culture. In other words, the Church emphasised that the teachings of Christianity brought contemporary culture into its proper fulfillment.

(b) Vedic Hinduism saw itself as providing the blue-print not only for religion but also for the varieties of cultural life. Indeed, for Vedic Hinduism, any separation between religion and culture was unknown. Culture was absorbed into religion and every cultural norm was legitimized through some religious practice or theological doctrine. For example, consider the question : is casteism a ‘religious’ or a ‘cultural’ system? From the perspective of Vedic Hinduism, one can only reply that this antithesis is misleading : casteism is at the same time both a religious and a cultural system.

(C)

Religion Above Culture

We now move into the third type. Those who follow this type agree with people in the second group on one point : religion is the fulfilment of culture. But they disagree with them on this point : there is a sharp discontinuity between religion and culture, and in this they agree with those in the first group. In other words, one cannot pass from religion and culture and vice versa as easily as in the case of, for example, Vedic Hinduism. There is therefore in religion something which does not follow immediately from culture. Religion is at the same time both continuous with and discontinuous with culture. Culture indeed leads men and women to religion but only in a partial, preliminary, and fragmented sense. A great leap is required if a person wants to move from culture to religion. True culture is possible only in the higher light of religious values.

Here are two examples :

(a) The ascetic tradition of Hinduism can be given as a good example of this type. Culture is not denounced as evil (as in the Type (A) above) but neither is there a direct step from culture to religion (as in the Type (B) above). Indeed, religion requires a rejection of certain elements of culture, which is good in itself (which is why the sannyasi is the world-renouncer), so that religious life requires a reordering of one’s value-system.

(b) Theravada Buddhism is another example of this type. In Thailand and Burma, Buddhism exists more or less harmoniously with various Hindu gods/goddesses and also belief in spirits (Burmese : nats). But it is emphasised repeatedly that the true Buddhist is not one who is immersed in the worship of gods and goddesses; the latter is a kind of ladder that one must throw away after one has reached the correct enlightenment. Thus Theravada Buddhism has a dialectical relation to the cultural life based on the Hinduism of the Ramayana and the Mahabharata : it both affirms the latter at a ‘lower’ level and rejects them at a ‘higher’ level.

(D)

Religion as Transformer of Culture

Those who fall in this group believe that religion has a conversionist function. We can better understand the claims of the people who belong to this group by contrasting their views with those of the previous ones.

In contrast to Type (A), those in this group argue that it is not enough simply to reject culture as devilish and move away from it. Rather, the diabolic elements in this culture must be transformed in the light of religious values.

In contrast to Type (B), it is argued that to say that one can move from culture to religion is to overlook the negative forms of injustice and inequalities that might be prevalent in culture. For example, slavery or patriarchy as a cultural institution can be uprooted only if there is some discontinuity between religion and culture. If religion is identified with culture without remainder, there remains no justification for opposing slavery or patriarchy.

In contrast to Type (C), it is argued that this answer is ultimately similar to Type (A). It is not enough to point out the discontinuities between religion and culture, the former should also be geared to removing the inequalities and the social injustices that are embodied in the latter.


With this survey, let me move on to make the following observations.

Though I started off by talking about Islam, it will be noticed that I have not mentioned Islam in any of the types so far. What we see from the above survey is that every religion has many strands in it, which is why we cannot claim that we have found the correct relation between a specific religion and culture. For example, I claimed that certain strands of Christianity can be placed in Type (A) (e.g.monastic Christianity) and other strands in Type (B) (e.g. the Holy Roman Empire). Similarly, there are elements of Hinduism which can be placed under Type (B) (e.g. Vedic Hinduism) and there are other elements in it which can be brought under Type (C) (e.g. ascetic Hinduism). In other words, we cannot provide a definite answer to this relation simply because no religion is a monolithic entity. There are complex strands within any religion and some of these strands may even contradict one another in certain respects. (To take just two examples, one can think of the endless debates over ‘idol-worship’ across the different traditions of Hinduism, and the question of whether Sufism is ‘orthodox’ Islam.)

What this means is also that we cannot say that there is only one way of conceptualising this relation in the case of Islam : we can place Islam both under Type (A) and Type (D). Islamic civilisation of the Baghdad Caliphate can perhaps be placed under Type (B). Type (A) is manifested in Islam’s vigorous denunciation (and destruction) of 'idol-worshipping' elements of surrounding culture. Type (D) is shown in the idea of an Islamic theocracy : every element of culture must be transformed in the light of Islamic doctrines.

Now one explanation for the strained relations between 'Islam and the West' is the following. ‘The West’, in general, has become very wary of systems that conceptualise the relation between ‘culture’ and ‘religion’ under Type (D). The notion that religion is a force that can transform culture is widely regarded as a reactionary one. Indeed, in the contemporary 'West', the preferred model seems to be some 'privatised' form of Type (B). Many a westerner will say : ‘I don’t care if you are religious so long as you do not go round disrupting and criticising my cultural values, whatever these may be. Religion is good as it is, but please do not let it interfere with my private life.’ This is something that Type (D) vigorously opposes : all cultural values without the light of religion are corrupt and vitiated by satanic forces.

In other words, one reason for the conflict between 'Islam and the West' is a difference of opinion over the importance that should be given to Type (D). ‘The West’ tends to reject Type (D) whereas it seems that Type (D) is almost required by the internal ‘logic’ of Islam. Islam is not, of course, the only religion that requires a Type (D) understanding of the relation between religion and culture : two other examples that come to mind immediately are John Calvin’s theocracy in Geneva and Ashokan Buddhism. Because of a long history of religious wars and oppression, however, ‘the West’ has made a decisive move away from Type (D) and religion has been stripped of all powers and channels to transform culture. A strict demarcation between the ‘religious’ and the ‘cultural’ spheres has been made : the former belongs to ‘private inner’ space and the latter to ‘public national’ space. In this situation, the rise of Islamic states under Type (D) which is regarded as confusing these two spaces heightens the opposition between ‘Islam and the West’.

I have said that the contemporary west broadly accepts Type (B). It looks at Type (A) as belonging to an age of persecution and religious tyranny. Now because of the conceptual similarity between Type (D) and Type (A), the 'West' feels that Islam can easily slip from Type (D) to Type (A), where Type (A) is equated with versions of ‘fundamentalisms’.

In truth, however, fundamentalism is possible even under Type (B). For example, contemporary Hindu fundamentalism is best placed not under Type (A) but under Type (B). Hindu fundamentalism does not reject culture but requires that it be absorbed into a certain specific understanding of what ‘Hinduism’ is. The problem is heightened by the fact that although critics of this fundamentalism can complain that Hinduism is being ‘politicised’, in truth there is no straightforward difference between ‘religion’, ‘culture’ and ‘politics’ in traditional Hinduism. Hindu fundamentalists can therefore claim that their interpretation of Hinduism is the traditional one, that is, in Hinduism, religion, culture and politics are intertwined. Another example of Type (B) relates to the socio-religious problems of the Middle East. The intimate connection between religion, land and culture in Israel and Palestine can be understood as a manifestation of this type.

To conclude then, I agree that an opposition between ‘Islam and the West’ is a genuine one. It is wrong, however, to think of this only as a modern contemporary phenomenon for it is as old as the Crusades. It is also wrong to think, however, that this opposition will always lead to ‘closure’ on all sides. The Mediaeval ages were the time of the Crusades, but they were also the time when a Moorish civilisation flourished. Indeed, Mediaeval Spain was one of the few times and places when Jews, Muslims and Christians lived together in harmony. This should not lead us to a facile optimism that another such culture will soon be formed, but it is only to serve as a reminder that oppositions need not always lead to a total breakdown in communication. Secondly, instead of talking about a clash between ‘civilisations’ one should rather talk about differences relating to the above types of conceptualising the relation between ‘religion’ and ‘culture’. ‘Civilisations’ do not exist in abstracto, they are not ‘things’ over and against people who have certain patterns of socio-religious behaviour, and indeed many of our problems begin precisely when we try to think of them as monolithic entities opposing one another.


Wednesday, December 29, 2004

The Heart of Emptiness Posted by Hello



(1)

Who shall know when suffering shall end ?
Perhaps suffering is just another illusion?
What, then, shall I tell them ---
They who spend autumn evenings
On the other side of those mountains
Weaving garlands out of the fallen flowers?

(2)

Is there no way
Out of the great circle of doubt?
Perhaps the only answer
Is the silent bridge
Over the noisy chasm
Some shall cross it
Others shall say
That the bridge does not exist
And yet perhaps the bridge itself shall remain
Till the last traveller in this world has turned to dust.






The Death of God Posted by Hello




Is God dead?

This is a question that I have been thinking about for almost ten years now, and especially so in the last four years. I think that the main reason why I found this question so attractive in the first place was the fact that it smacks of the paradoxical. If the word ‘God’ is defined as ‘that eternal reality which cannot die’, then the question becomes ‘Has that reality which cannot die indeed suffered death?’, and with my personal fascination for paradoxical statements I often caught myself mulling over this one. Over the years, I began to realise that there is no universal consensus not only on how the divine is to be conceptualised but also on the question of how the very term ‘God’ should be defined. That is, to a Muslim the word ‘God’ refers to a Personal reality who is all-Compassionate and to whom the entire creation must bow down with an attitude of loving adoration, to an Advaitin Hindu ‘God’ is at best a concession to the ignorant minds of unenlightened human beings, and to a Buddhist ‘God’ is simply one more finite being trapped within the miserable cycle of rebirth. Most of these ‘established’ religions also fall into one or the other of a variety of –isms : if you are a pantheist, ‘God’ is ultimately this very world in some form or the other, if you are a monist, the ultimate reality is One in a manner that is ineffable, and if you are a theist, there is a supreme Person who lovingly condescends to the depths of the human condition.

Consequently, the question ‘Does God exist?’ over which rivers of ink have been spilled is an extremely problematical question. It is so because the person who asks this question (usually) assumes that s/he and the person to whom it is put are referring to the same entity by the word ‘God’. For example, both a Jew and a scientist may agree that ‘God’ does exist, but whereas for the former the term ‘God’ refers to the personal Lord of Israel, the God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob, for the latter ‘God’ is simply the ordered and harmonious functioning of the universe. Therefore, though the Jew and the scientist (apparently) agree with each other, this agreement is a superficial one : it does not address the more critical issue of what precisely they mean by the term ‘God’. In other words, the innocent-looking question ‘Does God exist?’ is potentially misleading unless it is put in this form, ‘What do you mean the term ‘God’?’ I have taken the example of a Jew and a scientist for this precise reason that Einstein was such a scientist who, though he was Jewish, did not believe in God as the personal Lord of Israel : for him, ‘God’ was just a name given to the never-failing harmony of the cosmos ruled by universal laws. Therefore both Einstein and an ‘orthodox’ Jew can agree that ‘God’ exists and yet disagree radically over what the term ‘God’ refers to.

Nevertheless, to make the discussion more specific let us define the term ‘God’ to mean : ‘a Personal reality who has created the world, sustains it at every moment of its existence, wishes to enter into a personal relationship with the different beings that constitute it and draws these beings towards the final goal of communion with Him/Herself.’

Is this God dead in today’s world?

A proper and exhaustive reply to such a question would demand volumes in paper, reviewing all the possible answers that have been given to it. Though such is not my intent here, I shall briefly consider three of the usual objections.


Objection 1 : ‘Science has disproved God’.

People who put forward this argument are usually suffering from a bad bout of intellectual laziness. This argument assumes that human beings have arrived at a universal consensus not only over what ‘science’ is but also over the process through which science ‘proves/disproves’ the existence of certain realities. (That is, it is much easier to claim that we have been blessed with the touchstone of the ‘scientific method’ than to actually describe how this method operates.) True, science has disproved the existence of unicorns but when it comes to terms such as ‘God’ it is simply quite out of its league. It is often forgotten in this connection that there is a crucial distinction that must be made between ‘science’ and ‘scientism’. The former may be defined as : ‘a tool which helps us to build up, piece-by-piece, through a processual investigation, a coherent picture of the world from the smaller bits of information that we have painstakingly garnered from controlled experiments conducted under specific conditions’. This is quite a ‘weak’ claim, and since the term ‘God’ does not refer to a reality on which human beings can experiment ‘science’ must simply remain silent on this matter, claiming neither that it has ‘proved’ (or can ‘prove’) God’s existence nor that it has ‘disproved’ God’s existence. This is a healthy agnosticism that accepts the limitations of ‘science’ as a cognitive tool and makes no rash extrapolations beyond its restricted field. ‘Scientism’, however, makes a much ‘stronger’ claim : ‘this tool called science is the only one that gives us a privileged access onto reality, and all other world-views that espouse other tools must be declared to be deviant, delinquent, archaic, mediaeval, reactionary, anti-humanistic, anti-progressive and superstitious’.

The basic question, however, is this : ‘Can scientism give a non-circular argument in its favour?’ In other words, if someone has not already accepted ‘scientism’ how would s/he know that ‘scientism’ is the only doorway to reality? Take a parallel case, the famous example of the ‘positivist’ dictum : ‘Do not accept anything that is not verifiable empirically.’ It sounds like good advice, and indeed it is in most cases, but trouble starts brewing when we ask : ‘Why should we accept this dictum since this dictum itself is not empirically verifiable?’‘Scientism’ has a similar problem of ‘justifiying’ itself. In other words, ‘scientism’ is what can only be called a ‘faith’, meaning by ‘faith’ not a ‘blind acceptance of anything that goes’ but a ‘a certain perspective through which a human being looks out into the world’. That is, ‘scientism’ is logically on the same level as any other faith which proclaims that it possesses the only correct perspective on the world, whatever this faith may be, Islam, Marxism, eco-feminism, Mormonism, Jainism, atheism and so on.

Of course, what I have said just now would be anathema to all proponents of ‘scientism’ especially because they want to claim that their ‘scientism’ is not a faith like the world-religions like Christianity and world-views like Marxism. There is, however, no easy way out of wriggling out of the conclusion that ‘scientism’ is indeed in the same boat with all other faiths. This does not in itself mean that we must reject ‘scientism’ (any more than we should reject the other faiths), only that ‘scientism’ cannot claim any immunity for itself with a ‘holier than thou’ attitude towards the other faiths.

In other words, we may, if we want to, say that ‘Scientism has disproved God’ but to say this is not to make a ‘scientific’ statement, it is to make a ‘faith-declaration’. Once again, there is nothing wrong with making such declarations, but what must be understood clearly that is that there is nothing ‘scientific’ about the above claim.

Objection 2: ‘God is an invention of psychologically weak people.’

Next, this argument makes an unwarranted leap from psychology to what may be called ‘ontology’, that is, to what really exists. The basic question in this context is not whether people who pray to God are psychologically weak (or strong) but whether God exists or not. Let us say that a woman prays to God only when she is distressed : this bare fact is not enough in itself to prove that God does not exist. The mere fact that a daughter goes to her mother only when she needs money does not prove that her mother does not exist. Such would be the case only if there was some independent means of proof : say, a death certificate signed by a doctor, an obituary in a newspaper and so on. (In the same way, a theist can argue that the fact that a certain woman prays to God only when she is scared of failing her exams does not prove that God does not exist : it only proves that the woman is operating with an immature understanding of God as a ‘grand mechanic’ who fiddles with the cosmic levers in a whimsical manner. Most religions such as Christianity have emphasised that there are two kinds of devotion, a lower one and a higher one. The lower type is the one in which a person prays, ‘God, grant me three cars, two sons and four hotels’, the higher is the one characterised by the prayer, ‘Not my will but Thy will shall be done.’)

However, let us accept for a moment the claim that people who do not believe in God are indeed those who are psychologically strong. Apart from the fact that this statement assumes too naively that psychologists have come to the final consensus on how to ‘measure’ psychological strength or weakness, one might want to know if what is being declared here is an equation of ‘truth’ with ‘psychological strength’. That is, is it a fact that whatever is stated by people who are psychologically ‘strong’ becomes through that mere connection something that must be certified as ‘true’? (Moreover, who are the psychologically ‘strong’ here? Even if we accept that atheists are psychologically ‘strong’, who exactly are the atheists that we are talking about? An American university professor and a Russian communist may both be atheists, but the latter can have serious doubts about the psychological ‘strength’ of the former.)

Though we must indeed accept that people who make true statements are usually not those who are on the verge of a nervous breakdown, to make such a straightforward equation is to overlook the fact that some of the greatest mistakes (such as the acceptance of the heliocentric theory, the phlogiston theory and so on) have been made by both psychologically ‘strong’ and ‘weak’ people. In short, then, the mere statement of psychological ‘strength’ or ‘weakness’ is not enough in itself to prove or disprove the existence of anything. (Besides, what about those painters, poets, writers and so on who were reviled as mad during their life-times? Does their lack of psychological ‘strength’ invalidate their claims about the nature of reality? Indeed, the study of the history of science will show that the very progress of science has depended on the ‘madness’ of some of its foundational figures. The proponent of ‘scientism’ may retort that this is ‘madness for a higher cause’, but this will be paralleled at once by the theist who will argue that the mystic too has a ‘madness for the highest cause of God.’ That is, the debate is not any more over sanity or insanity but over what ‘reality’ is fundamentally like.)

There is one further weakness with this argument : it can be turned around on the proponent of ‘scientism’ by the theist. Let us allow the theist to put forward the following case : ‘It is you, the proponent of ‘scientism’, who is bent on remaining psychologically ‘weak’. This is because true psychological ‘strength’ lies in expanding, training, refining and developing the capacities of the mind to such an extent that the mind becomes more and more receptive to supra-empirical reality. By assuming right at the beginning that such a reality cannot exist in principle you are simply blocking yourself off from the possibility of attaining the most fulfilling truth that liberates human existence in all its dimensions.’

In other words, the question is not that of who is psychologically strong or weak but that of whether or not there is in fact such a supra-empirical reality. If there indeed is such a reality, it will be the proponent of ‘scientism’ who is psychologically weak in not being able to develop his/her mind to ‘tune into’ into that reality, but if it is the other way round, then indeed it is the theist who is psychologically weak by believing in things that do not exist.

Take for example the celebrated arguments put forward by Freud which might be paraphrased thus : ‘Human beings need God because the notion of God gives them mental strength. Such people are afraid to step out into the ‘real world’ and to live in the harshness of that non-divine world where there is no such entity.’

Implicit in such arguments is the massive assumption that the proponent of ‘scientism’ has actually come to the final truth of what the ‘real world’ is. That nothing of this sort has happened can be seen simply by considering this fact : a Neo-Darwinian in Oxford, a post-modernist in California, a Marxist in Vienna, a Freudian in London and a capitalist in Canada may all be proponents of ‘scientism’ but they will have virtually insurmountable disagreements with one other regarding what the ‘real world’ is. If indeed that is the case, it is far from being a settled matter that the proponents of ‘scientism’ have given the final verdict on the nature of ultimate reality.

In any case, as I have shown above, ‘scientism’ cannot have a non-circular ‘proof’ to defend itself : the proponent can merely say, ‘Scientism is the only avenue to reality because there can be no other avenue.’ Or to put it more bluntly, ‘Scientism is the final truth because I say so.’ In other words, for such a proponent it is not even a matter of ‘proof’ that the term ‘God’ does not refer to a substantial reality; God is not allowed to exist by the very definition of the term.

A final comment in this regard. Most people who put forward this argument assume that the following two things are mutually exclusive : on the one hand, the fact that X exists and on the other hand, the fact that I derive psychological strength from the existence of X. In other words, they jump from the fact that the notion of God makes me feel psychologically healthy to the claim that therefore God cannot exist. This does not follow, however. If I feel psychologically happy in the company of my friend John, this psychological state in itself does not disprove John’s non-existence. One would have to appeal to some independent means of proving that the man called John in fact does not exist and is a mere figment of my imagination. Similarly, the theist can offer the following reply, ‘Of course, my belief in God gives me psychological strength. Why should this not be the case if God indeed is the ultimate reality? But this psychological stability does not disprove the divine existence any more than the psychological confidence that I obtain from the laws of my country proves that these laws do not exist.’

Now the proponent of ‘scientism’ can put forward this argument against the theist : ‘That may be the case, but I can prove that the laws of your country exist in a way that you cannot prove that your God exists.’ This is a completely valid argument and to reply to it the theist will need adequate reasons to justify his/her belief in God : I shall return to this point later. What I wish to emphasise at this point is simply the fact that psychological states of ‘strength’ or ‘weakness’ are not conclusive proofs to the effect that a certain entity does or does not exist.

Objection 3 : ‘Science will one day disprove God’s existence’

Carrying over from the previous two objections, we can now see that this objection should properly be re-stated as, ‘Scientism will one day disprove God’s existence’. Now put in this manner this sounds even more like a ‘faith-declaration’. Compare it to two other equally well-known faith-declarations, one of Christianity and the other of Marxism : ‘In the last day, God will be all and all’ and ‘In the future, the state will wither away and human relationships will become transparent’ respectively. In other words, like all other faiths, ‘scientism’ too makes ‘predictions’ about the future and puts forward its distinctive vision of the ‘final destiny’ of human beings. Once again, there is nothing wrong with all that, so long as it is remembered that, like other faiths, ‘scientism’ too is a faith which has a specific view of the future.

However, how ‘justified’ is ‘scientism’ in making that claim?

A lot depends on what is meant by the term ‘God’ here. Most people who seem to believe that ‘God’ will be dead in another fifty years of ‘scientific’ research seem to mean by this term something of this sort : ‘a finite reality who is sitting in the heavens up-there, who can be located within a definite spatio-temporal zone, a grand old Father with a white beard, and who now and then pleases human beings with nice goodies when He is sufficiently placated.’

There is only one problem, however, with this description : the serious enquirer into this matter would be hard-pressed to find any major theologian, whether s/he is Christian, (Vedantic) Hindu, Jewish or Muslim, who would agree with it. In other words, none of these faiths teaches that God is a finite entity who is localisable in space and time in the manner in which we say, ‘The sky is above my head’ or ‘I am drinking my tea now.’ That is, our usual vocabulary of space and time does not apply to the reality of God, and to claim that ‘science’, that is, that dimension of human knowledge that deals only with objects within space and time, can disprove the existence of something not within these limits is to make a claim that is grossly illogical. (The cosmonaut Yuri Gagarin is said to have made the declaration, ‘When I went up to space, I did not find God there. Hence God does not exist.’ This simply shows Marxist naivety at its worst : as I have said above, no major theologian has ever claimed that God is a finite object ‘sitting up there in the sky’. In this particular case, it is not Gagarin but the theologian who will have the last laugh at his lack of ‘translation’ skills.)

It would seem, however, that there is one way out for the proponent of ‘scientism’ who could claim : ‘Anything that is not within the limits of space and time does not exist.’

Induced to put forward this proposition, the proponent shows all too clearly the faith-nature of his/her claim. The above statement is brought forward in the manner of an axiom : but how indeed would we prove this axiom to be ‘true’? That is, it is one thing to say, ‘About things outside space and time I know nothing of and I chose to keep my mouth shut’ (this, in effect, was the Buddha’s position on such matters with the crucial exception of the state of Nirvana) but quite another to say, ‘By using science which deals with things within space and time I have proved that things outside space and time cannot exist’. The former is simply a claim based on (learned) ignorance, the latter is one that attempts in vain to cross the boundaries of its own discipline.

In other words, it is not a matter of time (another fifty years?) before God is dead, as so many people seem to believe. If God is an extra-spatio-temporal being, we may refuse to accept the possibility of such a mode of existence, but in no case can we claim that ‘science’ has actually disproved the existence such a reality for as we have seen above ‘science’, by definition, deals only with objects within space and time. (The case would be similar to that of a fish-scientist who might claim that because every fish lives in water, there can be no extra-aqueous reality. The fish-scientist should properly say, ‘There can be no extra-aqueous entity that is fish-like’ and not, ‘Since everything around me is fish-like, this in itself proves that there can be nothing that is non-fish-like.’ In the latter case, the fish-scientist is merely suffering from a piscean myopia.)

It is now time to make some summary comments on this interchange of views. First, the discerning reader will have noted that the main thrust of this essay is not to ‘prove’ or ‘disprove’ the existence of God. If anything, it has tried to show that there are major obstacles to be crossed even before such an attempt can be made. Second, it has insisted that there are no non-circular ‘scientific’ arguments to the extent that God cannot exist. That is, many arguments which are put forward in the intellectual bazaar as ‘scientific’ happen to accept the axiom that an extra-spatio-temporal entity cannot exist in principle, but someone who does not accept this axiom need not accept the conclusions that the proponent of ‘scientism’ arrives at. The proponent of course very cleverly disguises the axiomatic nature of this claim by hiding behind the protective smoke-screen of ‘science’ and by stating that ‘scientism’ is ‘self-evident’, ‘universally valid’ and ‘rationally perspicacious’. That is, by appealing to the authority of ‘science’, which is an authority that most people in our generation accept almost unthinkingly, the proponent of ‘scientism’ seeks, under its aegis, to make the unwarranted leap from ‘science’ to the axiom that ‘science is the only avenue into reality’. As I have emphasised above, anyone who does not accept this axiom is entirely free to reject the conclusions that the proponent of ‘scientism’ claims to have arrived at in a ‘scientific’ manner.

Thirdly, however, let me draw attention to some of the formidable problems facing the theist. So far, I have been trying to show that though ‘scientism’ has attained a near cult-status for the proverbial ‘man in the street’ by employing various kinds of intellectually dishonest means (such as the propaganda through the media that ‘God is dead’), it is not enough for the theist to expose the fundamental circularity of this allegedly ‘scientific’ position. (That is, to put it in a very terse form, ‘scientism’ cannot prove itself to be ‘scientific’.) In other words, the arguments have been of a (formally) negative nature so far : but now the theist will have to press on with some positive arguments as to why someone should accept the existence of God. This is a task which I do not intend to carry on here but make the following two points.

Firstly, it is not sufficient to have cleared the ground of simplistic ‘scientistic’ arguments for one will have to move beyond the logical possibility that an extra-spatio-temporal entity can exist to the positive claim that such an entity does exist. To this effect, one can appeal to the various kinds of experiences that human beings have reported of having been ‘in touch’ with such an entity down the centuries. The usual reply to such experiences is, ‘Such experiences cannot take place in principle.’ As it must be clear by now, this reply ultimately stems from the stance of ‘scientism’ that I have outlined above, a stance which rules out from the very beginning the existence of anything that is not confined to space and time. However, if someone, like the theist, does not accept the axiom that everything that exists is necessarily spatio-temporal there is no logical reason why such experiences must be rejected out of hand.

Secondly, one will have to move on to the ‘bolder’ claim that not only such an entity exists but that this entity has indeed, on its own wish, initiated a process of inter-personal communication with humanity. Here we are finally on distinctively ‘religious’ terrain : here ‘logical proof’ must flow into what is called ‘faith’. The latter must not be misunderstood as the ‘blind acceptance of what does not exist’ (this is the definition of ‘faith’ in the cheap propaganda of ‘scientism’ which wilfully refuses to accept that it itself is a faith), but as the ‘vision of the flickering lights giving a sense of direction towards the goal that lies ahead, though the actual path to be traversed remains largely unknown’. With the latter definition of ‘faith’ (and I have tried to show that ‘scientism’ too is a faith in this sense) the theist can move ahead on the way with the faith that the extra-spatio-temporal reality has indeed sent out an ‘offer’ to enter into some kind of ‘communion’ with it, though the exact nature of this ‘offer’ and the ‘communion’ will be understood in distinctive ways by the follower of Islam, Christianity, devotional Hinduism and Judaism. Why these different religious systems understand these basic issues in diverse ways is of course a crucial matter for another discussion, but this diversity does not affect the basic point I am making here : it is not the case that ‘faith’ is the ‘attitude of illiterate, reality-scared, demented, psychotic, and superstitious people’ for there are valid grounds on which such ‘faith’ is based.

Let me therefore end with a discussion two of these ‘valid grounds’. Firstly, there are no logically convincing reasons why an extra-spatio-temporal being cannot exist in principle. This is the ‘negative’ thrust of the argument. Secondly, all world-views depend on certain axioms on which they are based and this applies to as diverse systems as ‘scientism’, Marxism, Islam, atheism, Mormonism, ‘liberalism’, Satanism, Keynesianism, and so on. To take up the case of Marxism, for example, one does not become a Marxist at one stroke and on ‘one fine morning’. One first starts with a somewhat hazy understanding of the axioms of Marxism, for example, the law of dialectical materialism. Only gradually over a period of a few years does one learn to look at the world through the ‘spectacles’ of this law, and to see this law being able to describe ‘reality’ as seen by him/her. That is, there is a spiralling process of interaction between a set of axioms and the world-view which is founded on it. This applies to all world-views, and the (sometimes painstaking) process of accepting any of these world-views starts with the ‘faith’ in the foundational axioms (‘faith’ being understood as I have defined it above). Now it is crucial to note that the theist too is operating on similar principles. S/he starts with the basic axiom, ‘ An extra-spatio-temporal being can exist’ and then goes ahead to see the ‘world’ more and more in terms of this axiom. There is nothing ‘irrational’ or ‘illogical’ about this because this is precisely the manner in which the proponents of ‘scientism’, Marxism, atheism, ‘humanism’, ‘secularism’ and so on too come to see the ‘world’.

To conclude then, in the debate over God/not-God two regulative points must be operative throughout. Firstly, everyone involved in it must be aware of the fundamentally axiomatic nature of his/her world-view. The proponent of ‘scientism’, for example, must not be allowed to get away with the ‘holier-than-thou’ claim that s/he offers a ‘view from nowhere’ that is non-axiomatic and that can be (indeed, must be) accepted by all ‘rational’ people. Secondly, this debate is not one of seeking ‘knock-down proofs’ for either theism or atheism because I have shown above both the atheist and the theist come to their distinctive world-views in logically the same manner, and the discussion is consequently centred not around the ‘crusading’ notion of ‘the champions of modern rationality battling against the tribes of primitive superstition’ but over diverging fundamental axioms. For the proponent of ‘scientism’ who merely states that no supra-spatio-temporal entity can exist without giving further arguments as to why one should accept this axiom, his/her case does not even get off the ground. The same applies, incidentally, to the theist who simply repeats that such an entity may exist without being able to provide any positive arguments to support this axiom. Thirdly, to carry on from the second point, the notion of the antagonistic polarisation between science as ‘rational’ and religion as ‘irrational’ must be given up, for the betterment of both ‘science’ and ‘religion’. Only in this way can people realise both that ‘religion’ has a distinctive perspective onto reality (though this does not mean that they have to become ‘religious’ or that ‘religion’ is the only perspective) and that a ‘science’ that has arrived at the horizons of its conceptual limitations is one that remains vigorous through its involvement with the basic question, ‘Why does anything exist at all?’
The Wholeness of Perfection Posted by Hello


Generally speaking, the term ‘perfection’ has been understood in two different ways : as the fulfillment of one specific goal or the realisation of a multi-levelled wholeness. The distinction between the two is not an absolute one, and is rather one of difference in emphasis. That is, there is a subtle intertwining of these two somewhat differing understandings of what ‘perfection’ is.

The first way to think of ‘perfection’ is to set before oneself a specific aim and direct all of one's energies, mental, psychical and physical towards it. That desired end could be anything really : passing an exam, bringing up a daughter, painting a masterpiece, or improving one's proficiency in a certain language. On the other hand, what is called the ‘mystical way’ is related to the second understanding of ‘perfection’ : the attainment of a wholeness that encompasses various dimensions. One reads of mystics claiming (in the Roman-Catholic/Sufi/Advaita-Vedanta traditions), through their distinctive vocabulary, that they have reached ‘rock-bottom’, meaning that they have experienced a fleeting foretaste of a (com-)union with the reality that lies underneath and beyond whatever we can see, hear, and touch. The intensity of the experience fades away, but the experience itself is not forgotten. It leaves an indelible impression on the mind and the heart of the mystic, and gives her a new orientation with which she looks out at the world. The world is then no more a mere set of objects to be consumed one after the other, but is instead seen as the locus of the presence that she had experienced in that moment of supreme intensity.

The mystic sees the world with a new pair of eyes. In one sense, she sees the ‘same’ world that we do, and yet, in another sense, it is a different world from ours. For us, the world is usually a random collection of odds and ends, a blooming and buzzing confusion, an arena of misery and pain that we try to make sense of. For the mystic, in contrast, there lies the obscure but immoveable faith, that the light that had overpowered and illuminated her is the same light that shines through the various layers of our limited empirical existence. Life is no more a uni-linear and dreary sequence of objects to be possessed and discarded one after the other, but a web of multi-layered experiences patterned around a centre shrouded in unapproacheable light.

But does it all ‘make sense’? I have tried to give a summary description of how some mystics have reported their experiences, but to those who have not had such experiences, there are two, and only two, possible ways of receiving such claims. One is to simply reject all of them as the outpourings of possessed, demented, and neurotic minds. Living as we do in a post-Freudian era, this is definitely one possible reception of such claims. It is only in the last century that we have become aware of the great extent to which genuinely neurotic experiences have in the past been disguised as ‘mystical’. Hence, it is important to exercise a cautious skepticism towards such expressions; after all, there is no end to men and women claiming to be ‘god-possessed’. (The term ‘god-possessed’ itself can mean different things to different people. The philosopher Baruch Spinoza was once described as being ‘god-drunk’.) However, it may not be possible to write off all such experiences as emerging from psychical imbalances. This is especially so in the case of those mystics whose lives have been so completely changed by their experiences that instead of castigating 'the world' as the locus of evil and demoniac forces, they have rather turned back to the world to truly enjoy its beauty, and exhibited through their own lives their belief that there is an elusive centre which weaves together the various strands of our lives into a harmonising tapestry which remains hidden from the direct sight of our eyes. This second reaction could therefore be to follow these mystics as our fellow-travellers on our long, weary but not cheerless journeys towards the quest for ‘perfection’. We could think of them as the fore-runners, people who have gone ahead of us into the far country and returned to tell us about it.

In other words, the mystical search for ‘perfection’ is a transfiguration and a fulfillment of what we usually mean by the term. ‘Perfection’ is no more seen in passive terms as involving a static and completed ‘I’ that simply absorbs the world to itself. This could be called the ‘accumulative’ understanding of perfection; it assumes that the ‘I’ is perfect-in-itself, and that what is missing from the picture is the other ‘I’ to be possessed or grasped. The mystical understanding, as I have described it above, subtly but surely changes this understanding of ‘perfection’. It starts not with a completed ‘I’, but beginning with an ‘I’ that will always remain in some sense a fragmented and broken entity directs it towards the healing vision that shines through it and beyond it and guides it towards ever-richening forms of wholeness.

But even if we are to accept what the mystics claim to have experienced, why is it not the case that all of us do not have these experiences too? Does not the very fact that only a few mystics undergo such experiences invalidate them? Although that is a powerful argument against uncritically accepting anything whatsoever that we read in ‘mystical literature’, this does not in itself show that such claims must be rejected. Take the case of John who is a fan of Richard Wagner, and who has a friend who regards himself as tone-deaf when it comes to music. Now if both of them are seated in a room and an opera of Wagner's is played on the radio, John will undergo certain experiences which he will never be able to express exhaustively in words to his friend, simply because something will always be lost in this translation of a musical experience into words. Moreover, even if John makes a sincere attempt, he might not be able to put across to his friend what Wagner's music ‘feels like’, simply because his friend has no ear for music at all. In just the same way, mystics may be those people who have developed certain human sensitivities to such a refined level that they are responsive to influences that we shall hastily, without any ‘second thoughts’, shut off from our lives. A person who is tone-deaf when it comes to music may not be able to experience any delight in an opera, but that does not in itself prove that musical excellence is non-existent. In the same way, non-mystics may be people who have consistently refused to open themselves up to a presence that was always subtly trying to draw them out-of-themselves. This whole argument does not settle either way the matter between mystics and non-mystics, but what it does show is that the mere fact that mystical experiences are rare and hard to come by does not in itself invalidate them.

But how shall we explain the fact that most mystics seem to have led pain-racked and tormented lives, lives interspersed only rarely with moments of uplifting joy? One way of explaining this is to refer to the painful awareness that many mystics share of the shattered nature of the ‘I’ : it is this awareness that lends so much pathos to the mystical path. For those of us who are not mystics, it is also our inability to look into ourselves and to realise that the ‘I’ is a project to be achieved painfully through various human experiences that sets off the mystical path as something alien, cold, distant, insane, and even dangerous. In contrast, it is their tragic sensitivity towards the incompleteness of their human search that gives mystics the aura of mental-imbalancedness. Having received the gracious presence that redeems all suffering by working through it, they are pained at the realisation that it is mortally impossible to live continually in conscious knowledge of that presence. The most that can be done is to live with the powerful memories and hope, without ceasing, that the glimmerings that shine through the dark night will blossom into the glorious resplendence of the coming dawn.





 
Free FAQ Database from Bravenet Free FAQ Database from Bravenet.com
The WeatherPixie